Distinguishing Westphalian and Weberian Sovereignty

Westphalian sovereignty is understood as a normative and explanatory approach to state power and legitimacy, considering non-interference as the governing distinction between the domestic state and the international system
Article by Jasper Wiggins
Image: Leviathan, Thomas Hobbes
Distinguishing Westphalian and Weberian Sovereignty
Australian Political Analysis Review - Open Source Independent Education
Westphalian sovereignty is understood as a normative and explanatory approach to state power and legitimacy, considering non-interference as the governing distinction between the domestic state and the international system (Lake, 2009, pg.44, 53). Westphalian sovereignty entitled a state to exclusive sovereignty over its territory. This principle was influenced by Thomas Hobbes’ (1901) ‘Levithan’ analogy, conceiving sovereignty as constituting social contract (pg.95). For realists, monopoly over violence was necessary to enforce civil society, whereas liberals also converged, assuming this as conducive to the civil institutions to promote cooperation as a form of protection distinguished from nature (Blaug and Schwarzmantel, 2016, 174-75 & 120-21).
On the contrary, Weberian sovereignty considered a state’s monopoly on violence as problematic to state power if it compromised its citizens rights, suggesting that infringements could de-legitimise sovereignty. Hobson (2000) also critiqued Westphalian sovereignty as causing a rift between ‘state-central’ domestic agential power and ‘non-state’ actors, inferring a responsibility for international intervention (pg.4). This was materialised in the Responsibility to Protect (R2P) principles governing sovereignty as the right the protection of citizens without violence. Consequently, for Marxists and Liberals, Weberian sovereignty should be viewed as the reflection of social forces rather than state as a neorealist body pursuing its interests over individual or collective rights (Cox, 1981, pg.138-40).
Bibliography
Lake, David A. (2009). ‘The State and International Relations', in Christian Reus-Smit, and Duncan Snidal (eds), The Oxford Handbook of International Relations, Oxford Academic, https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199219322.003.0002
Hobbes, T. (1901). ‘Hobbes’ Levithan reprinted from the edition of 1651 with an Essay by the late W.G Pogson Smith’ Oxford: Clarendon Press (1909). http://files.libertyfund.org/files/869/0161_Bk.pdf
Blaug, R, and Schwarzmantel, J. (2016). ‘Rousseau the Social Contract’ in Democracy’ In Democracy: A Reader Second Edition. Columbia University Press, New York
Blaug, R, and Schwarzmantel, J. (2016). ‘John Locke The Second Treastie on Government’ In Democracy: A Reader Second Edition. Columbia University Press, New York
Hobson, J. (2000). “What’s at Stake in the Second State Debate?’ Concepts and Issues.’ In The State and International Relations.1-14. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Cox, R. (1981). ‘Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory. Millenium 10 (2) London School of Economics 126-55
Jasper Wiggins
30/10/2024
The Social Contract captures the relationship between consent to govern by the individual, and the extent to which the State exercises authority. Both Kant and Locke examine conditional express and tacit consent and how it compares with obliged moral duty. Kant's view towards the role of the State differs from Locke's notion that authority to establish a society is granted by the consent of the majority, rather than constitution. Ultimately, Kant's morally regulative approach challenges Locke, asserting that the empowerment of constitution requires the incorporation of popular obedience, to uphold enforceable legal authority.
Article by Jasper Wiggins
Article by Jasper Wiggins
Article by Jasper Wiggins
Explore More on Ideology
Explore More On Ideology




Search Projects and Articles



Search Projects and Articles
About and Contact
Contribute
myBLOG